In the Age of Computer
Networks
Thursday, April 19,
2001 5:00 - 7:00
p.m.
Transcript
The following is an edited
transcript.
|
DAVID THORBURN, moderator: Our speaker today,
Richard Stallman, is a legendary figure in the computing world, and
my experience in trying to find a respondent to share the podium
with him was instructive. One distinguished MIT professor told me
that Stallman needs to be understood as a charismatic figure in a
biblical parable – a kind of Old Testament anecdote-lesson. “Imagine,” he said, “a Moses or a Jeremiah –
better a Jeremiah.” And
I said, “Well, that’s very admirable. |
|
That sounds wonderful. It confirms my sense of the
kind of contribution he has made to the world. Then why are you reluctant
to share the podium with him?”
His answer: “Like Jeremiah or Moses, he would simply
overwhelm me. I won’t
appear on the same panel him, but if you asked me to name five
people alive in the world who have truly helped us all, Richard
Stallman would be one of them.” |
RICHARD
STALLMAN:
I should [begin by explaining why I have refused to allow
this Forum to be web cast],
in case it wasn’t clear fully what the issue is: The software they use for
web broadcasting requires the user to download certain software in
order to receive the broadcast. That software is not free
software. It’s
available at zero price but only as an executable, which is a
mysterious bunch of numbers.
|
|
What it does is secret. You can’t study it; you
can’t change it; and you certainly can’t publish it in your own
modified version. And
those are among the freedoms that are essential in the definition of
“free software.”
|
So if I am to be an honest advocate for free
software, I can hardly go around giving speeches, then put pressure
on people to use non-free software. I’d be undermining my own
cause. And if I don’t
show that I take my principles seriously, I can’t expect anybody
else to take them seriously.
However, this speech is not about free
software. After I’d been working on the free-software movement for
several years and people started using some of the pieces of the GNU
operating system, I began getting invited to give speeches [at
which] . . . people started asking
me: “Well, how do the
ideas about freedom for software users generalize to other kinds of
things?”
And, of course, people asked
silly questions like, “Well, should hardware be free?” “Should this microphone be
free?”
|
Well, what does that mean? Should you be free to copy
it and change it? Well,
as for changing it, if you buy the microphone, nobody is going to
stop you from changing it.
And as for copying it, nobody has a microphone copier. Outside of “Star Trek,”
those things don’t exist.
Maybe some day there’ll be nanotechnological analyzers and
assemblers, and it really will be possible to copy a physical
object, and then these issues of whether you’re free to do that will
start being really important.
We’ll see agribusiness companies trying to stop people from
copying food, and that will become a major political issue, if that
technological capability will ever exist. I don’t know if it will;
it’s just speculation at this point.
But for other kinds of information, you can
raise the issue because any kind of information that can be stored
on a computer, conceivably, can be copied and modified. So the ethical issues of
free software, the issues of a user’s right to copy and modify
software, are the same as such questions for other kinds of
published information.
Now I’m not talking about private information, say, personal
information, which is never meant to be available to the public at
all. I’m talking about
the rights you should have if you get copies of published things
where there’s no attempt to keep them
secret.
In order to explain my ideas on the subject,
I’d like to review the history of the distribution of information
and of copyright. In
the ancient world, books were written by hand with a pen, and
anybody who knew how to read and write could copy a book about as
efficiently as anybody else.
Now somebody who did it all day would probably learn to be
somewhat better at it, but there was not a tremendous
difference. And because
the copies were made one at a time, there was no great economy of
scale. Making ten
copies took ten times as long as making one copy. There was also nothing
forcing centralization; a book could be copied anywhere.
Now because of this technology, because it
didn’t force copies to be identical, there wasn’t in the ancient
world the same total divide between copying a book and writing a
book. There are things
in between that made sense.
They did understand the idea of an author. They knew, say, that this
play was written by Sophocles but in between writing a book and
copying a book, there were other useful things you could do. For instance, you could copy
a part of a book, then write some new words, copy some more and
write some new words and on and on. This was called “writing a
commentary” -- that was a common thing to do – and these
commentaries were
appreciated. |
You could also copy a passage out of one
book, then write some other words, and copy a passage from another
book and write some more and so on, and this was making a
compendium. Compendia
were also very useful.
There are works that are lost but parts of them survived when
they were quoted into other books that got to be more popular than
the original. Maybe
they copied the most interesting parts, and so people made a lot of
copies of these, but they didn’t bother copying the original because
it wasn’t interesting enough.
Now as far as I can tell, there was no such
thing as copyright in the ancient world. Anyone who wanted to copy a
book could copy the book.
Later on, the printing press was developed and books started
to be copied on the printing press. Now the printing press was
not just a quantitative improvement in the ease of copying. It affected different kinds
of copying unevenly because it introduced an inherent economy of
scale. It was a lot of
work to set the type and much less work to make many identical
copies of the page. So
the result was that copying books tended to become a centralized,
mass-production activity.
Copies of any given book would probably be made in only a few
places.
It also meant that ordinary readers couldn’t
copy books efficiently.
Only if you had a printing press could you do that. So it was an industrial
activity.
Now for the first few centuries of printing,
printed books did not totally replace hand-copying. Hand-copied books were still
made, sometimes by rich people and sometimes by poor people. The rich people did this to
get an especially beautiful copy that would show how rich they were,
and poor people did it because maybe they didn’t have enough money
to buy a printed copy but they had the time to copy a book by
hand. As the song says,
“Time ain’t money when all you got is
time.”
So hand-copying was still done to some
extent. I think it was
in the 1800s that printing actually got to be cheap enough that even
poor people could afford printed books if they were
literate. |
Now copyright was developed along with the
use of the printing press and given the technology of the printing
press, it had the effect of an industrial regulation. It didn’t restrict what
readers could do; it restricted what publishers and authors could
do. Copyright in
England was initially a form of censorship. You had to get government
permission to publish the book. But the idea has
changed. By the time of
the U.S. Constitution, people came to a different idea of the
purpose of copyright, and I think that that idea was accepted in
England as well.
For the U.S. Constitution it was proposed
that authors should be entitled to a copyright, a monopoly on
copying their books.
This proposal was rejected. Instead, a crucially
different proposal was adopted which is that, for the sake of
promoting progress, Congress could optionally establish a copyright
system that would create these monopolies. So the monopolies, according
to the U.S. Constitution, do not exist for the sake of those who own
them; they exist for the sake of promoting the progress of
science. The monopolies
are handed out to authors as a way of modifying their behavior to
get them to do something that serves the public.
So the goal is more written and published
books which other people can then read. And this is believed to
contribute to increased literary activity, increased writing about
science and other fields, and society then learns through this. That’s the purpose to be
served. The
creation of private monopolies was a means to an end only, and the
end is a public end.
Now copyright in the age of the printing
press was fairly painless because it was an industrial
regulation. It restricted only the
activities of publishers and authors. Well, in some strict sense,
the poor people who copied books by hand may have been infringing
copyright, too. But
nobody ever tried to enforce copyright against them because it was
understood as an industrial
regulation. |
Copyright in the age of the printing press
was also easy to enforce because it had to be enforced only where
there was a publisher, and publishers, by their nature, make
themselves known. If
you’re trying to sell books, you’ve got to tell people where to come
to buy them. You don’t
have to go into everybody’s house to enforce
copyright.
And, finally, copyright may have been a
beneficial system in that context. Copyright in the U.S. is
considered by legal scholars as a trade, a bargain between the
public and authors. The
public trades away some of its natural rights to make copies, and in
exchange gets the benefit of more books’ being written and
published.
Now, is this an advantageous trade? Well, when the general
public can’t make copies because they can only be efficiently made
on printing presses – and most people don’t own printing presses –
the result is that the general public is trading away a freedom it
is unable to exercise, a freedom that is of no practical value. So if you have something
that is a byproduct of your life and it’s useless and you have the
opportunity to exchange it for something else of any value, you’re
gaining. So that’s why
copyright may have been an advantageous trade for the public in that
time.
But the context is changing, and that has to
change our ethical evaluation of copyright. Now the basic principles of
ethics are not changed by advances in technology; they’re too
fundamental to be touched by such contingencies. But our decision about any
specific question is a matter of the consequences of the
alternatives available, and the consequences of a given choice may
change when the context changes. That is what is happening in
the area of copyright law because the age of the printing press is
coming to an end, giving way gradually to the age of the computer
networks. |
Computer networks and digital information
technology are bringing us back to a world more like the ancient
world where anyone who can read and use the information can also
copy it and can make copies about as easily as anyone else could
make them. They are
perfect copies and they’re just as good as the copies anyone else
could make. So the
centralization and economy of scale introduced by the printing press
and similar technologies is going away.
And this changing context changes the way
copyright law works.
You see, copyright law no longer acts as an industrial
regulation; it is now a Draconian restriction on a general
public. It used to be a
restriction on publishers for the sake of authors. Now, for practical purposes,
it’s a restriction on a public for the sake of publishers. Copyright used to be fairly
painless and uncontroversial.
It didn’t restrict the general public. Now that’s not true. If you have a computer, the
publishers consider restricting you to be their highest
priority. Copyright was
easy to enforce because it was a restriction only on publishers who
were easy to find and what they published was easy to see. Now the copyright is a
restriction on each and everyone of you. To enforce it requires
surveillance – an intrusion – and harsh punishments, and we are
seeing these being enacted into law in the U.S. and other
countries.
And copyright used to be, arguably, an
advantageous trade for the public to make because the public was
trading away freedoms it couldn’t exercise. Well, now it can exercise
these freedoms. What do
you do if you have been producing a byproduct which was of no use to
you and you were in the habit of trading it away and then, all of a
sudden, you discover a use for it? You can actually consume it,
use it. What do you
do? You don’t trade at
all; you keep some. And
that’s what the public would naturally want to do. That’s what the public does
whenever it’s given a chance to voice its preference; it keeps some
of this freedom and exercises it. Napster is a big example of
that, the public deciding to exercise the freedom to copy instead of
giving it up. So the
natural thing for us to do to make copyright law fit today’s
circumstances is to reduce the amount of copyright power that
copyright owners get, to reduce the amount of restriction that they
place on the public and to increase the freedom that the public
retains.
|
But this is not what the publishers want to
do. What they want to
do is exactly the opposite.
They wish to increase copyright powers to the point where
they can remain firmly in control of all use of information. This has led to laws that
have given an unprecedented increase in the powers of
copyright. Freedoms
that the public used to have in the age of the printing press are
being taken away.
For instance, let’s look at e-books. There’s a tremendous amount
of hype about e-books; you can hardly avoid it. I took a flight in Brazil
and in the in-flight magazine, there was an article saying that
maybe it would take 10 or 20 years before we all switched to
e-books. Clearly, this
kind of campaign comes from somebody paying for it. Now why are they doing
that? I think I
know. The reason is
that e-books are the opportunity to take away some of the residual
freedoms that readers of printed books have always had and still
have – the freedom, for instance, to lend a book to your friend or
borrow it from the public library or sell a copy to a used bookstore
or buy a copy anonymously, without putting a record in the database
of who bought that particular book. And maybe even the right to
read it twice.
These are freedoms that the publishers would
like to take away, but they can’t do this for printed books because
that would be too obvious a power-grab and would raise an outcry. So
they have found an indirect strategy: First, they obtain the
legislation to take away these freedoms for e-books when there are
no e-books; so there’s no controversy. There are no pre-existing
users of e-books who are accustomed to their freedoms and will
defend them. That they
obtained with the Digital Millennium Copyright Act in 1998. Then they introduce e-books
and gradually get everybody to switch from printed books to e-books
and eventually the result is, readers have lost these freedoms
without ever having an instant when those freedoms were being taken
away and when they might have fought back to retain
them. |
We see at the same time efforts to take away
people’s freedom in using other kinds of published works. For instance, movies that
are on DVDs are published in an encrypted format that used to be
secret – it was meant to be secret – and the only way the movie
companies would tell you the format, so that you could make a DVD
player, was if you signed a contract to build certain restrictions
into the player, with the result that the public would be stopped
even from fully exercising their legal rights. Then a few clever
programmers in Europe figured out the format of DVDs and they wrote
a free software package that would read a DVD. This made it possible to use
free software on top of the GNU Plus Linux operating system to watch
the DVD that you had bought, which is a perfectly legitimate thing
to do. You ought to be
able to do that with free software.
But the movie companies objected and they
went to court. You see,
the movie companies used to make a lot of films where there was a
mad scientist and somebody was saying, “But, Doctor, there are some
things Man was not meant to know.” They must have watched their
own films too much because they came to believe that the format of
DVDs is something that Man was not meant to know. And they obtained a ruling
for total censorship of the software for playing DVDs. Even making a link to a site
where this information is legally available outside the U.S. has
been prohibited. An
appeal has been made against this ruling. I signed a
friend-of-the-court brief in that appeal, I’m proud to say, although
I’m playing a fairly small role in that particular
battle.
The U.S. government intervened directly on
the other side. This is
not surprising when you consider why the Digital Millennium
Copyright Act was passed in the first place. The reason is the campaign
finance system that we have in the U.S., which is essentially
legalized bribery where the candidates are bought by business before
they even get elected.
And, of course, they know who their master is – they know
whom they’re working for – and they pass the laws to give business
more power.
What will happen with that particular
battle, we don’t know.
But meanwhile Australia has passed a similar law and Europe
is almost finished adopting one; so the plan is to leave no place on
earth where this information can be made available to people. But the U.S. remains the
world leader in trying to stop the public from distributing
information that’s been
published. |
The U.S. though is not the first country to
make a priority of this.
The Soviet Union treated it as very important. There this unauthorized
copying and re-distribution was known as Samizdat and to
stamp it out, they developed a series of methods: First, guards watching every
piece of copying equipment to check what people were copying to
prevent forbidden copying.
Second, harsh punishments for anyone caught doing forbidden
copying. You could sent to Siberia. Third, soliciting informers,
asking everyone to rat on their neighbors and co-workers to the
information police.
Fourth, collective responsibility – You! You’re going to watch that
group! If I catch any
of them doing forbidden copying, you are going to prison. So watch them hard. And, fifth, propaganda,
starting in childhood to convince everyone that only a horrible
enemy of the people would ever do this forbidden
copying.
The U.S. is using all of these measures
now. First, guards
watching copying equipment.
Well, in copy stores, they have human guards to check what
you copy. But human
guards to watch what you copy in your computer would be too
expensive; human labor is too expensive. So they have robot
guards. That’s the
purpose of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act. This software goes in your
computer; it’s the only way you can access certain data and it stops
you from copying.
There’s a plan now to introduce this
software into every hard disk, so that there could be files on your
hard disk that you can’t even access except by getting permission
from some network server to access the file. And to bypass this software
or even tell other people how to bypass it is a
crime.
Second, harsh punishments. A few years ago, if you made
copies of something and handed them out to your friends just to be
helpful, this was not a crime; it had never been a crime in the
U.S. Then they made it
a felony, so you could be put in prisons for years for sharing with
your neighbor.
Third, informers. Well, you may have seen the
ads on TV, the ads in the Boston subways asking people to rat on
their co-workers to the information police, which officially is
called the Software Publishers
Association. |
And fourth, collective responsibility. In the U.S., this has been
done by conscripting Internet service providers, making them legally
responsible for everything their customers post. The only way they can avoid
always being held responsible is if they have an invariable
procedure to disconnect or remove the information within two weeks
after a complaint. Just
a few days ago, I heard that a clever protest site criticizing City
Bank for some of its nasty policies was disconnected in this
way. Nowadays, you
don’t even get your day in court; your site just gets
unplugged.
And, finally, propaganda, starting in
childhood. That’s what
the word “pirate” is used for.
If you’ll think back a few years, the term “pirate” was
formerly applied to publishers that didn’t pay the author. But now it’s been turned
completely around. It’s
now applied to members of the public who escape from the control of
the publisher. It’s
being used to convince people that only a nasty enemy of the people
would ever do this forbidden copying. It says that “sharing with
your neighbor is the moral equivalent of attacking a ship.” I hope that you don’t agree
with that and if you don’t, I hope you will refuse to use the word
in that way.
So the publishers are purchasing laws to
give themselves more power.
In addition, they’re also extending the length of time the
copyright lasts. The
U.S. Constitution says that copyright must last for a limited time,
but the publishers want copyright to last forever. However, getting a
constitutional amendment would be rather difficult, so they found an
easier way that achieves the same result. Every 20 years they
retroactively extend copyright by 20 years. So the result is, at any
given time, copyright nominally lasts for a certain period and any
given copyright will nominally expire some day. But that expiration will
never be reached because every copyright will be extended by 20
years every 20 years; thus no work will ever go into the public
domain again. This has
been called “perpetual copyright on the installment
plan.”
The law in 1998 that extended copyright by
20 years is known as the “Mickey Mouse Copyright Extension Act”
because one of the main sponsors of this law was Disney. Disney realized that the
copyright on Mickey Mouse was going to expire, and they don’t want
that to ever happen because they make a lot of money from that
copyright. |
Now the original title of this talk was
supposed to be “Copyright and Globalization.” If you look at
globalization, what you see is that it’s carried out by a number of
policies which are done in the name of economic efficiency or
so-called free-trade treaties, which really are designed to give
business power over laws and policies. They’re not really about
free trade. They’re
about a transfer of power:
removing the power to decide laws from the citizens of any
country who might conceivably consider their own interests and
giving that power to businesses who will not consider the interests
of those citizens.
Democracy is the problem in their view, and
these treaties are designed to put an end to the problem. For instance, NAFTA actually
contains provisions, I believe, allowing companies to sue another
government to get rid of a law that they believe is interfering with
their profits in the other country. So foreign companies have
more power than citizens of the country.
There are attempts being made to extend this
beyond NAFTA. For
instance, this is one of the goals of the so-called free trade area
of the Americas, to extend this principle to all the countries in
South America and the Caribbean as well, and the multilateral
agreement on investment was intended to spread it to the whole
world.
One thing we’ve seen in the ‘90s is that
these treaties begin to impose copyright throughout the world, and
in more powerful and restrictive ways. These treaties are not
free-trade treaties.
They’re actually corporate-controlled trade treaties being
used to give corporations control over world trade, in order to
eliminate free
trade. |
When the U.S. was a developing country in
the 1800s, the U.S. did not recognize foreign copyrights. This was a decision made
carefully, and it was an intelligent decision. It was acknowledged that for
the U.S. to recognize foreign copyrights would just be
disadvantageous, that it would suck money out and wouldn’t do much
good.
The same logic would apply today to
developing countries but the U.S. has sufficient power to force them
to go against their interests.
Actually, it’s a mistake to speak of the interests of
countries in this context.
In fact, I’m sure that most of you have heard about the
fallacy of trying to judge the public interest by adding up
everybody’s wealth. If
working Americans lost $1 billion and Bill Gates gained $2 billion,
would Americans generally be better off? Would this be good for
America? Or if you look
only at the total, it looks like it’s good. However, this example really
shows that the total is the wrong way to judge because Bill Gates
really doesn’t need another $2 billion, but the loss of the $1
billion by other people who don’t have as much to start with might
be painful. Well, in a
discussion about any of these trade treaties, when you hear people
talk about the interests of this country or that country, what
they’re doing, within each country, is adding up everybody’s
income. The rich people
and the poor people are being added up. So it’s actually an excuse
to apply that same fallacy to get you to ignore the effect on the
distribution of wealth within the country and whether the treaty is
going to make that more uneven, as it has done in the
U.S.
So it’s really not the U.S. interest that is
being served by enforcing copyright around the world. It’s the interests of
certain business owners, many of whom are in the U.S. and some of
whom are in other countries.
It doesn’t, in any sense, serve the public
interest.
But what would make sense to do? If we believe in the goal of
copyright stated, for instance in the U.S. Constitution, the goal of
promoting progress, what would be intelligent policies to use in the
age of the computer network?
Clearly, instead of increasing copyright powers, we have to
pull them back so as to give the general public a certain domain of
freedom where they can make use of the benefits of digital
technology, make use of their computer networks. But how far should that
go? That’s an
interesting question because I don’t think we should necessarily
abolish copyright totally.
The idea of trading some freedoms for more progress might
still be an advantageous trade at a certain level, even if
traditional copyright gives up too much freedom. But in order to think about
this intelligently, the first thing we have to recognize is, there’s
no reason to make it totally uniform. There’s no reason to insist
on making the same deal for all kinds of work.
|
In fact, that already isn’t the case because
there are a lot of exceptions for music. Music is treated very
differently under copyright law. But the arbitrary insistence
on uniformity is used by the publishers in a certain clever
way. They pick some
peculiar special case and they make an argument that, in that
special case, it would be advantageous to have this much
copyright. And then
they say that for uniformity’s sake, there has to be this much
copyright for everything.
So, of course, they pick the special case where they can make
the strongest argument, even if it’s a rather rare special case and
not really very important overall.
But maybe we should have that much copyright
for that particular special case. We don’t have to pay the
same price for everything we buy. A thousand dollars for a new
car might be a very good deal.
A thousand dollars for a container of milk is a horrible
deal. You wouldn’t pay
the special price for everything you buy in other areas of
life. Why do it
here?
So we need to look at different kinds of
works, and I’d like to propose a way of doing
this.
This includes recipes, computer programs,
manuals and textbooks, reference works like dictionaries and
encyclopedias. For all
these functional works, I believe that the issues are basically the
same as they are for software and the same conclusions apply. People should have the
freedom even to publish a modified version because it’s very useful
to modify functional works.
People’s needs are not all the same. If I wrote this work to do
the job I think needs doing, your idea as a job you want to do may
be somewhat different.
So you want to modify this work to do what’s good for
you. At that point,
there may be other people who have similar needs to yours, and your
modified version might be good for them. Everybody who cooks knows
this and has known this for hundreds of years. It’s normal to make copies
of recipes and hand them out to other people, and it’s also normal
to change a recipe. If
you change the recipe and cook it for your friends and they like
eating it, they might ask you, “Could I have the recipe?” Then maybe you’ll write down
your version and give them copies. That is exactly the same
thing that we much later started doing in the free-software
community. |
So that’s one class of work. The second class of
work is works whose purpose is to say what certain people
think. Talking about
those people is their purpose.
This includes, say, memoirs, essays of opinion, scientific
papers, offers to buy and sell, catalogues of goods for sale. The whole point of those
works is that they tell you what somebody thinks or what somebody
saw or what somebody believes.
To modify them is to misrepresent the authors; so modifying
these works is not a socially useful activity. And so verbatim
copying is the only thing that people really need to be allowed to
do.
The next question is: Should people have the right
to do commercial verbatim copying? Or is non-commercial
enough? You see, these
are two different activities we can distinguish, so that we can
consider the questions separately – the right to do non-commercial
verbatim copying and the right to do commercial verbatim
copying. Well, it might
be a good compromise policy to have copyright cover commercial
verbatim copying but allow everyone the right to do non-commercial
verbatim copying. This
way, the copyright on the commercial verbatim copying, as well as on
all modified versions – only the author could approve a modified
version – would still provide the same revenue stream that it
provides now to fund the writing of these works, to whatever extent
it does.
By allowing the non-commercial verbatim
copying, it means the copyright no longer has to intrude into
everybody’s home. It becomes an industrial regulation again, easy to
enforce and painless, no longer requiring Draconian punishments and
informers for the sake of its enforcement. So we get most of the
benefit – and avoid most of the horror – of the current
system. |
The third category of works is aesthetic or
entertaining works, where the most important thing is just the
sensation of looking at the work. Now for these works, the
issue of modification is a very difficult one because on the one
hand, there is the idea that these works reflect the vision of an
artist and to change them is to mess up that vision. On the other hand, you have
the fact that there is the folk process, where a sequence of people
modifying a work can sometimes produce a result that is extremely
rich. Even when you
have artists’ producing the works, borrowing from previous works is
often very useful. Some
of Shakespeare’s plays used a story that was taken from some other
play. If today’s
copyright laws had been in effect back then, those plays would have
been illegal. So it’s a
hard question what we should do about publishing modified versions
of an aesthetic or an artistic work, and we might have to look for
further subdivisions of the category in order to solve this
problem. For example,
maybe computer game scenarios should be treated one way; maybe
everybody should be free to publish modified versions of them. But perhaps a novel should
be treated differently; perhaps for that, commercial publication
should require an arrangement with the original
author.
Now if commercial publication of these
aesthetic works is covered by copyright, that will give most of the
revenue stream that exists today to support the authors and
musicians, to the limited extent that the present system supports
them, because it does a very bad job. So that might be a
reasonable compromise, just as in the case of the works which
represent certain people.
If we look ahead to the time when the age of
the computer networks will have fully begun, when we’re past this
transitional stage, we can envision another way for the authors to
get money for their work.
Imagine that we have a digital cash system that enables you
to get money for your work.
Imagine that we have a digital cash system that enables you
to send somebody else money through the Internet; this can be done
in various ways using encryption, for instance. And imagine that verbatim
copying of all these aesthetic works is permitted. But they’re written in such
a way that when you are playing one or reading one or watching one,
a box appears on the side of your screen that says, “Click here to
send a dollar to the author,” or the musician or whatever. And it just sits there; it
doesn’t get in your way; it’s on the side. It doesn’t interfere with
you, but it’s there, reminding you that it’s a good thing to support
the writers and the musicians.
|
So if you love the work that you’re reading
or listening to, eventually you’re going to say, “Why shouldn’t I
give these people a dollar?
It’s only a dollar.
What’s that? I
won’t even miss it.”
And people will start sending a dollar. The good thing about this is
that it makes copying the ally of the authors and musicians. When somebody e-mails a
friend a copy, that friend might send a dollar, too. If you really love it, you
might send a dollar more than once and that dollar is more than
they’re going to get today if you buy the book or buy the CD because
they get a tiny fraction of the sale. The same publishers that are
demanding total power over the public in the name of the authors and
musicians are giving those authors and musicians the shaft all the
time.
I recommend you read Courtney Love’s article
in “Salon” magazine, an article about pirates that plan to use
musicians’ work without paying them. These pirates are the record
companies that pay musicians 4% of the sales figures, on the
average. Of course, the
very successful musicians have more clout. They get more than 4% of
their large sales figures, which means that the great run of
musicians who have a record contract get less than 4% of their small
sales figures.
Here’s the way it works: The record company
spends money on publicity and they consider this expenditure as an
advance to the musicians, although the musicians never see it. So nominally when you buy a
CD, a certain fraction of that money is going to the musicians, but
really it isn’t.
Really, it’s going to pay back the publicity expenses, and
only if the musicians are very successful do they ever see any of
that money.
The musicians, of course, sign their record
contracts because they hope they’re going to be one of those few who
strike it rich. So
essentially a rolling lottery is being offered to the musicians to
tempt them. Although
they’re good at music, they may not be good at careful, logical
reasoning to see through this trap. So they sign and then
probably all they get is publicity. Well, why don’t we give them
publicity in a different way, not through a system that’s based on
restricting the public and a system of the industrial complex that
saddles us with lousy music that’s easy to sell. Instead, why not make the
listener’s natural impulse to share the music they love the ally of
the musicians? If we
have this box that appears in the player as a way to send a dollar
to the musicians, then the computer networks could be the mechanism
for giving the musicians this publicity, the same publicity which is
all they get from record contracts
now. |
We have to recognize that the existing
copyright system does a lousy job of supporting musicians, just as
lousy as world trade does of raising living standards in the
Philippines and China.
You have these enterprise zones where everyone works in a
sweatshop and all of the products are made in sweatshops. I knew that globalization
was a very inefficient way of raising living standards of people
overseas. Say, an
American is getting paid $20 an hour to make something and you give
that job to a Mexican who is getting paid maybe six dollars a day,
what has happened here is that you’ve taken a large amount of money
away from an American worker, given a tiny fraction, like a few
percents, to a Mexican worker and given back the rest to the company. So if your goal is to raise
the living standards of Mexican workers, this is a lousy way to do
it.
It’s interesting to see how the same
phenomenon is going on in the copyright industry, the same general
idea. In the name of
these workers who certainly deserve something, you propose measures
that give them a tiny bit and really mainly prop up the power of
corporations to control our lives.
If you’re trying to replace a very good
system, you have to work very hard to come up with a better
alternative. If you
know that the present system is lousy, it’s not so hard to find a
better alternative; the standard of comparison today is very
low. We must always
remember that when we consider issues of copyright
policy.
So I think I’ve said most of what I want to
say. I’d like to
mention that tomorrow is Phone-In Sick Day in Canada. Tomorrow is the beginning of
a summit to finish negotiating the free trade area of the Americas
to try to extend corporate power throughout additional countries,
and a big protest is being planned for Quebec. We’ve seen extreme methods
being used to smash this protest. A lot of Americans are being
blocked from entering Canada through the border that they’re
supposed to be allowed to enter through at any time. On the flimsiest of excuses,
a wall has been built around the center of Quebec to be used as a
fortress to keep protesters out. We’ve seen a large number of
different dirty tricks used against public protest against these
treaties. So whatever
democracy remains to us after government powers have been taken away
from democratically elected governors and given to businesses and to
unelected international bodies, whatever is left after that may not
survive the suppression of public protest against it.
I’ve dedicated 17 years of my life to
working on free software and allied issues. I didn’t do this because I
think it’s the most important political issue in the world. I did it because it was the
area where I saw I had to use my skills to do a lot of good. But what’s happened is that
the general issues of politics have evolved, and the biggest
political issue in the world today is resisting the tendency to give
business power over the public and governments. I see free software and the
allied questions for other kinds of information that I’ve been
discussing today as one part of that major issue. So I’ve indirectly found
myself working on that issue.
I hope I contribute something to the
effort. |
RESPONSE:
THORBURN: We’ll turn to the
audience for questions and comments in a moment. But let me offer a brief
general response. It
seems to me that the strongest and most important practical guidance
that Stallman offers us has two key elements. One is the recognition that old
assumptions about copyright, old usages of copyright are
inappropriate; they are challenged or undermined by the advent of
the computer and computer networks. That may be obvious, but it
is essential.
Second is the recognition that the digital
era requires us to reconsider how we distinguish and weigh forms of
intellectual and creative labor. Stallman is surely right
that certain kinds of intellectual enterprises justify more
copyright protection than others. Trying to identify systematically
these different kinds or levels of copyright protection seems
to me a valuable way to engage with the problems for intellectual
work posed by the advent of the
computer.
But I think I detect another theme that lies
beneath what Stallman has been saying and that isn’t really directly
about computers at all, but more broadly about questions of
democratic authority and the power that government and corporations
increasingly exercise over our lives. This populist and
anti-corporate side to Stallman’s discourse is nourishing but also
reductive, potentially simplifying. And it is also perhaps
overly idealistic.
For example, how
would a a
novelist or a poet or a songwriter or a musician or the author of an
academic textbook surivive in this brave new world where people are
encouraged but not required to pay authors. In other words, it seems to
me, the gap between existing practice and the visionary possibilities
Stallman speculates about is still immensely wide.
So I’ll conclude by asking if Stallman would
like to expand a bit on certain aspects of his talk and,
specifically, whether he has further thoughts about the way in which
what we’ll call “traditional creators” would be protected under his
copyright system. |
STALLMAN:
First of all, I have to point out that we shouldn’t use the
term “protection” to describe what copyright does. Copyright restricts
people. The term
“protection” is a propaganda term of the copyright-owning
businesses. The term
“protection” means stopping something from being somehow
destroyed. Well, I
don’t think a song is destroyed if there are more copies of it being
played more. I don’t
think that a novel is destroyed if more people are reading copies of
it, either. So I won’t
use that word. I think
it leads people to identify with the wrong
party.
Also, it’s a very bad idea to think about
intellectual property for two reasons: First, it prejudges the most
fundamental question in the area which is: How should these things be
treated and should they be treated as a kind of property? To use the term
“intellectual property” to describe the area is to presuppose the
answer is “yes,” that that’s the way to treat things, not some other
way.
Second, it encourages
over-generalization.
Intellectual property is a catch-all for several different
legal systems with independent origins such as, copyrights, patents,
trademarks, trade secrets and some other things as well. They are almost completely
different; they have nothing in common. But people who hear the term
“intellectual property” are led to a false picture where they
imagine that there’s a general principle of intellectual property
that was applied to specific areas, so they assume that these
various areas of the law are similar. This leads not only to
confused thinking about what is right to do, it leads people to fail
to understand what the law actually says because they suppose that
the copyright law and patent law and trademark law are similar,
when, in fact, they are totally
different.
So if you want to encourage careful thinking
and clear understanding of what the law says, avoid the term
“intellectual property.”
Talk about copyrights.
Or talk about patents.
Or talk about trademarks or whichever subject you want to
talk about. But don’t
talk about intellectual property. Opinion about intellectual
property almost has to be a foolish one. I don’t have an opinion
about intellectual property.
I have opinions about copyrights and patents and trademarks,
and they’re different.
I came to them through different thought processes because
those systems of law are totally
different.
Anyway, I made that digression, but it’s
terribly important.
So let me now get to the point. Of course, we can’t see now
how well it would work, whether it would work to ask people to pay
money voluntarily to the authors and musicians they love. One thing that’s obvious is
that how well such a system would work is proportional to the number
of people who are participating in the network, and that number, we
know, is going to increase by an order of magnitude over a number of
years. If we tried it
today, it might fail, and that wouldn’t prove anything because with
ten times as money people participating, it might work.
The other thing is, we do not have this
digital cash payment system; so we can’t really try it today. You could try to do
something a little bit like it. There are services you can
sign up for where you can pay money to someone – things like Pay
Pal. But before you can
pay anyone through Pay Pal, you have to go through a lot of
rigmarole and give them personal information about you, and they
collect records of whom you pay. Can you trust them not to
misuse that?
So the dollar might not discourage you, but
the trouble it takes to pay might discourage you. The whole idea of this is
that it should be as easy as falling off a log to pay when you get
the urge, so that there’s nothing to discourage you except the
actual amount of money.
And if that’s small enough, why should it discourage
you. We know, though,
that fans can really love musicians, and we know that encouraging
fans to copy and re-distribute the music has been done by some bands
that were, and are, quite successful like the “Grateful Dead.” They didn’t have any trouble
making a living from their music because they encouraged fans to
tape it and copy the tapes.
They didn’t even lose their record sales.
We are gradually moving from the age of the
printing press to the age of the computer network, but it’s not
happening in a day.
People are still buying lots of records, and that will
probably continue for many years – maybe forever. As long as that continues,
simply having copyrights that stIIill apply to commercial sales of
records ought to do about as good a job of supporting musicians as
it does today. Of
course, that’s not very good, but, at least, it won’t get any
worse. |
DISCUSSION:
QUESTION: [A comment and and question
about free downloading and about Stephen King’s attempt to market
one of his novels serially over the
web.]
STALLMAN: Yes, it’s interesting to
know what he did and what happened. When I first heard about
that, I was elated. I
thought, maybe he was taking a step towards a world that is not
based on trying to maintain an iron grip on the public. Then I saw that he had
actually written to ask people to pay. To explain what he did, he
was publishing a novel as a serial, by installments, and he said,
“If I get enough money, I’ll release more.” But the request he wrote was
hardly a request. It
brow-beat the reader.
It said, “If you don’t pay, then you’re evil. And if there are too many of
you who are evil, then I’m just going to stop writing this.”
Well, clearly, that’s not the way to make
the public feel like sending you money. You’ve got to make them love
you, not fear you.
SPEAKER: The details were that he
required a certain percentage – I don’t know the exact percentage,
around 90% sounds correct. – of people to send a certain amount of
money, which, I believe, was a dollar or two dollars, or somewhere
in that order of magnitude
You had to type in your name and your e-mail address and some
other information to get to download it and if that percentage of
people was not reached after the first chapter, he said that he
would not release another chapter. It was very antagonistic to
the public downloading it. |
QUESTION:
Isn’t the scheme where there’s no copyright but people are
asked to make voluntary donations open to abuse by people
plagiarizing?
STALLMAN: No. That’s not what I
proposed. Remember, I’m
proposing that there should be copyright covering commercial
distribution and permitting only verbatim re-distribution
non-commercially. So
anyone who modified it to put in a pointer to his website, instead
of a pointer to the real author’s website, would still be infringing
the copyright and could be sued exactly as he could be sued
today. |
QUESTION:
I see. So you’re
still imagining a world in which there is
copyright?
STALLMAN: Yes. As I’ve said, for those
kinds of works. I’m not
saying that everything should be permitted. I’m proposing to reduce
copyright powers, not abolish them.
THORBURN: I guess one question that
occurred to me while you were speaking, Richard, and, again, now
when you’re responding here to this question is why you don’t
consider the ways in which the computer, itself, eliminates the
middle men completely – in the way that Stephen King refused to do –
and might establish a personal
relationship.
STALLMAN: Well, they can and, in fact,
this voluntary donation is one –
THORBURN: You think of that as not
involving going through a publisher at
all?
STALLMAN: Absolutely not. I hope it won’t, you see,
because the publishers exploit the authors terribly. When you ask the publishers’
representatives about this, they say, “Well, yes, if an author or if
a band doesn’t want to go through us, they shouldn’t be legally
required to go through us.”
But, in fact, they’re doing their utmost to set it up so that
will not be feasible.
For instance, they’re proposing restricted copying media
formats and in order to publish in these formats, you’ll have to go
through the big publishers because they won’t tell anyone else how
to do it. So they’re
hoping for a world where the players will play these formats, and in
order to get anything that you can play on those players, it’ll have
to come through the publishers. So, in fact, while there’s
no law against an author or a musician publishing directly, it won’t
be feasible. There’s
also the lure of maybe hitting it rich. They say, “We’ll publicize
you and maybe you’ll hit it as rich as the Beatles.” Take your pick of some very
successful group and, of course, only a tiny fraction of musicians
are going to have that happen.
But they may be drawn by that into signing contracts that
will lock them down forever.
Publishers tend to be very bad at respecting
their contracts with authors.
For instance, book contracts typically have said that if a
book goes out of print, the rights revert to the author, and
publishers have generally not been very good about living up to that
clause. They often have
to be forced. Well,
what they’re starting to do now is use electronic publication as an
excuse to say that it’s never going out of print; so they never have
to give the rights back.
Their idea is, when the author has no clout, get him to sign
up and from then on, he has no power; it’s only the publisher that
has the power. |
QUESTION:
Would it be good to have free licenses for various kinds of
works that protect for every user the freedom to copy them in
whatever is the appropriate way for that kind of
work?
STALLMAN: Well, people are working on
this. But for
non-functional works, one thing doesn’t substitute for another. Let’s look at a functional
kind of work, say, a word processor. Well, if somebody makes a
free word processor, you can use that; you don’t need the non-free
word processors. But I
wouldn’t say that one free song substitutes for all the non-free
songs or that a one free novel substitutes for all the non-free
novels. For those kinds
of works, it’s different. So what I think we
simply have to do is to recognize that these laws do not deserve to
be respected. It’s not
wrong to share with your neighbor, and if anyone tries to tell you
that you cannot share with your neighbor, you should not listen to
him. |
QUESTION:
With regard to the functional works, how do you, in your own
thinking, balance out the need for abolishing the copyright with the
need for economic incentives in order to have these functional works
developed?
STALLMAN: Well, what we see is, first
of all, that this economic incentive is a lot less necessary than
people have been supposing.
Look at the free software movement where we have over 100,000
part-time volunteers developing free software. We also see that there are
other ways to raise money for this which are not based on stopping
the public from copying and modifying these works. That’s the interesting
lesson of the free software movement. Aside from the fact that it
gives you a way you can use a computer and keep your freedom to
share and cooperate with other people, it also shows us that this
negative assumption that people would never do these things unless
they are given special powers to force people to pay them is simply
wrong. A lot of people
will do these things.
Then if you look at, say, the writing of monographs which
serve as textbooks in many fields of science except for the ones
that are very basic, the authors are not making money out of
that. We now have a
free encyclopedia project which is, in fact, a commercial-free
encyclopedia project, and it’s making progress. We had a project for a GNU
encyclopedia but we merged it into the commercial project when they
adopted our license. In
January, they switched to the GNU-free documentation license for all
the articles in their encyclopedia. So we said, “Well,
let’s join forces with them and urge people to contribute to
them.” It’s called
“NUPEDIA,” and you can find a link to it, if you look at http://
www.gnu.org/encyclopedia.
So here we’ve extended the community development of a free
base of useful knowledge from software to encyclopedia. I’m pretty confident now
that in all these areas of functional work, we don’t need that
economic incentive to the point where we have to mess up the use of
these works.
THORBURN: Well, what about the other
two categories.
STALLMAN: For the other two classes of
work, I don’t know. I
don’t know whether people will write some day novels without
worrying about whether they make money from it. In a post-scarcity society,
I guess they would.
Maybe what we need to do in order to reach the post-scarcity
society is to get rid of the corporate control over the economy and
the laws. So, in
effect, it’s a chicken-or-the-egg problem, you know. Which do we do first? How do we get the world
where people don’t have to desperately get money except by removing
the control by business?
And how can we remove the control by business except -- Anyway, I don’t know, but
that’s why I’m trying to propose first a compromise copyright system
and, second, the voluntary payment supported by a compromise
copyright system as a way to provide a revenue stream to the people
who write those works. |
QUESTION:
How would you really expect to implement this compromise
copyright system under the chokehold of corporate interests on
American politicians due to their campaign-finance
system?
STALLMAN: It beats me. I wish I knew. It’s a terribly hard
problem. If I knew how
to solve that problem, I would solve it and nothing in the world
could make me prouder. |
QUESTION:.
How do you fight the corporate control? Because when you look at
these sums of money going into corporate lobbying in the court case,
it is tremendous. I
think the DECS case that you’re talking about is costing something
like a million-and-a-half dollars on the defense side. Lord knows what it’s costing
on the corporate side.
Do you have any idea how to deal with these huge sums of
money?
STALLMAN: I have a suggestion. If I were to suggest totally
boycotting movies, I think people would ignore that suggestion. They might consider it too
radical. So I would
like to make a slightly different suggestion which comes to almost
the same thing in the end, and that is, don’t go to a movie unless
you have some substantial reason to think it’s good. Now this will lead in
practice to almost the same result as a total boycott of Hollywood
movies. In extension,
it’s almost the same but, in intention, it’s very different. Now I’ve noticed that many
people go to movies for reasons that have nothing to do with whether
they think the movies are good. So if you change that, if
you only go to a movie when you have some substantial reason to
think it’s good, you’ll take away a lot of their
money.
THORBURN: One way to understand all of
this discourse today, I think, is to recognize that whenever radical,
potentially transforming technologies appear in society, there’s a
struggle over who controls them. We today are repeating
what has happened in the past.
So from this angle, there may not be a reason for despair, or
even pessimism, about what may occur in the longer run. But, in the shorter term,
struggles over the control of text and images, over all forms of
information are likely to be painful and extensive. For example, as a teacher of
media, my access to images has been restricted in recent years in a
way that had never been in place before. If I write an essay in which
I want to use still images, even from films, they are much harder to
get permission to use, and the prices charged to use those still
images are much higher – even when I make arguments about
intellectual inquiry and the the legal category of “fair use.” So I think, in this moment
of extended transformation, the longer-term prospects may, in fact,
not be as disturbing as what’s happening in the shorter term. But in any case, we need to
understand the whole of our contemporary experience as a renewed
version of a struggle over the control of technological resources
that is a recurring principle of Western
society.
It’s also essential to understand that the
history of older technologies is itself a complicated matter. The impact of the printing
press in Spain, for example, is radically different from its impact
in England or in France.
|
QUESTION:
One of the things that bothers me when I hear discussions of
copyright is that often they start off with, “We want a 180-degree
change. We want to do
away with any sorts of control.” It seems to me that part of
what lay under the three categories that were suggested is an
acknowledgement that there is some wisdom to copyright. Some of the critics of the
way copyright is going now believe that, in fact, it ought to be
backed up and function much more like patent and trademarks in terms
of its duration. I
wonder if our speaker would comment on that as a
strategy.
STALLMAN: I agree that shortening the
time span of copyright is a good idea. There is absolutely no need
in terms of encouraging publication for a possibility of copyrights’
lasting as much as 150 years, which, in some cases, it can under
present law. Now the
companies were saying that a 75-year copyright on a work made for
hire was not long enough to make possible the production of their
works. I’d like to
challenge those companies to present projected balance sheets for 75
years from now to back up that contention. What they really wanted was
just to be able to extend the copyrights on the old works, so that
they can continue restricting the use of them. But how you can encourage
greater production of works in the 1920s by extending copyright
today escapes me, unless they have a time machine somewhere. Of course, in one of their
movies, they had a time machine. So maybe that’s what
affected their thinking. |
QUESTION:
Have you given thought to extending the concept of “fair
use,” and are there any nuances there that you might care to lay out
for us?
STALLMAN: Well, the idea of giving
everyone permission for non-commercial verbatim copying of two kinds
of works, certainly, may be thought of as extending what fair use
is. It’s bigger than
what’s fair use currently. If your idea is that the public trades
away certain freedoms to get more progress, then you can draw the
line at various, different places. Which freedoms does the
public trade away and which freedoms does the public
keep? |
QUESTION:
To extend the conversation for just a moment, in certain
entertainment fields, we have the concept of a public
presentation. So, for
example, copyright does not prevent us from singing Christmas carols
seasonally but it prevents the public performance. And I’m wondering if it
might be useful to think about instead of expanding fair use to
unlimited, non-commercial, verbatim copying, to something less than
that but more than the present concept of fair
use.
STALLMAN: I used to think that that
might be enough, and then Napster convinced me otherwise because
Napster is used by its users for non-commercial, verbatim
re-distribution. The
Napster server, itself, is a commercial activity but the people who
are actually putting things up are doing so non-commercially, and
they could have done so on their websites just as easily. The tremendous excitement
about, interest in, and use of Napster shows that that’s very
useful. So I’m
convinced now that people should have the right to publicly
non-commercially, re-distributed, verbatim copies of
everything. |
QUESTION:
One analogy that was recently suggested to me for the whole
Napster question was the analogy of the public library. I suppose some of you who
have heard the Napster arguments have heard this analogy. I’m wondering if you would
comment on it. The
defenders of people who say Napster should continue and there
shouldn’t be restrictions on it sometimes say something like this:
“When folks go into the public library and borrow a book, they’re
not paying for it, and it can be borrowed dozens of times, hundreds
of time, without any additional payment. Why is Napster any
different?”
STALLMAN: Well, it’s not exactly the
same. But it should be
pointed out that the publishers want to transform public libraries
into pay-per-use, retail outlets. So they’re against public
libraries. |
QUESTION:
Can these ideas about copyright suggest any ideas for certain
issues about patent law such as making cheap, generic drugs for use
in Africa?
STALLMAN: No, there’s absolutely no
similarity. The issues
of patents are totally different from the issues of copyrights. The idea that they have
something to do with each other is one of the unfortunate
consequences of using the term “intellectual property” and
encouraging people to try to lump these issues together because, as
you’ve heard, I’ve been talking about issues in which the price of a
copy is not the crucial thing.
But what’s the crucial issue about making AIDS drugs for
Africa? It’s the price,
nothing but the price.
Now the issue I’ve been talking about arises
because digital information technology gives every user the ability
to make copies. Well,
there’s nothing giving us all the ability to make copies of
medicines. I don’t have
the ability to copy some medicine that I’ve got. In fact, nobody does; that’s
not how they’re made.
Those medicines can only be made in expensive factories and
they are made in expensive centralized factories, whether they’re
generic drugs or imported from the U.S. Either way, they’re going to
be made in a small number of factories, and the issues are simply
how much do they cost and are they available at a price that people
in Africa can afford.
So that’s a tremendously important issue,
but it’s a totally different issue. There’s just one area where
an issue arises with patents that is actually similar to these
issues of freedom to copy, and that is in the area of
agriculture. Because
there are certain patented things that can be copies, more or less –
namely, living things.
They copy themselves when they reproduce. It’s not necessarily exact
copying; they re-shuffle the genes. But the fact is, farmers for
millennia have been making use of this capacity of the living things
they grow to copy themselves.
Farming is, basically, copying the things that you grew and
you keep copying them every year. When plant and animal
varieties get patented, when genes are patented and used in them,
the result is that farmers are being prohibited from doing
this.
There is a farmer in Canada who had a
patented variety growing on his field and he said, “I didn’t do that
deliberately. The
pollen blew, and the wind in those genes got into my stock of
plants.” And he was
told that that doesn’t matter; he has to destroy them anyway. It was an extreme example of
how much government can side with a monopolist.
So I believe that, following the same
principles that I apply to copying things on your computer, farmers
should have an unquestioned right to save their seeds and breed
their livestock. Maybe
you could have patents covering seed companies, but they shouldn’t
cover farmers. |
QUESTION:
There’s more to making a model successful than just the
licensing. Can you
speak to that?
STALLMAN: Absolutely. Well, you know, I don’t know
the answers. But part
of what I believe is crucial for developing free, functional
information is idealism.
People have to recognize that it’s important for this
information to be free, that when the information is free, you can
make full use of it.
When it’s restricted, you can’t. You have to recognize that
the non-free information is an attempt to divide them and keep them
helpless and keep them down.
Then they can get the idea, “Let’s work together to produce
the information we want to use, so that it’s not under the control
of some powerful person who can dictate to us what we can
do.”
This tremendously boosts it. But I don’t know how much it
will work in various different areas, but I think that in the area
of education, when you’re looking for textbooks, I think I see a way
it can be done. There
are a lot of teachers in the world, teachers who are not at
prestigious universities – maybe they’re in high-school; maybe
they’re in college – where they don’t write and publish a lot of
things and there’s not a tremendous demand for them. But a lot of them are
smart. A lot of them
know their subjects well and they could write textbooks about lots
of subjects and share them with the world and receive a tremendous
amount of appreciation from the people who will have learned from
them. |
QUESTION:
That’s what I proposed.
But the funny thing is, I do know the history of
education. That’s what
I do – educational, electronic media projects. I couldn’t find an
example. Do you know of
one?
STALLMAN: No, I don’t. I started proposing this
free encyclopedia and learning resource a couple of years ago, and I
thought it would probably take a decade to get things rolling. Now we already have an
encyclopedia that is rolling.
So things are going faster than I hoped. I think what’s needed is for
a few people to start writing some free textbooks. Write one about whatever is
your favorite subject or write a fraction of one. Write a few chapters of one
and challenge other people to write the
rest. |
QUESTION:
Actually what I was looking for is something even more than
that. What’s important
in your kind of structure is somebody that creates an infrastructure
to which everybody else can contribute. There isn’t a K through 12
infrastructure out there in any place for a contribution for
materials.
I can get information from lots of places
but it’s not released under free licenses, so I can’t use it to make
a free textbook.
STALLMAN: Actually, copyright doesn’t
cover the facts. It
only covers the way it’s written. So you can learn a field
from anywhere and then write a textbook, and you can make that
textbook free, if you want. |
QUESTION: But I can’t write by myself all the
textbooks that a student needs going through
school.
STALLMAN: Well, it’s true. And I didn’t write a whole,
free operating system, either.
I wrote some pieces and invited other people to join me by
writing other pieces.
So I set an example.
I said, “I’m going in this direction. Join me and we’ll get
there.” And enough
people joined in that we got there. So if you think in terms of,
how am I going to get this whole gigantic job done, it can be
daunting. So the point
is, don’t look at it that way.
Think in terms of taking a step and realizing that after
you’ve taken a step, other people will take more steps and,
together, it will get the job done eventually.
Assuming that humanity doesn’t wipe itself
out, the work we do today to produce the free educational
infrastructure, the free learning resource for the world, that will
be useful for as long as humanity exists. If it takes 20 years to get
it done, so what? So
don’t think in terms of the size of the whole job. Think in terms of the piece
that you’re going to do.
That will show people it can be done, and so others will do
other pieces. |
|